Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2018 | 27 | 1 | 85–104

Article title

Epistemological Naturalness: What is a good heuristic strategy good for?

Authors

Content

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
According to the standard interpretation of Lewis’s theory of predicate meaning (the U&N theory), the naturalness of meaning candidates should be stated metaphysically  as a length of definition in terms of fundamental properties. Recently, Weatherson has criticized the U&N theory and argued that the criterion of naturalness should be stated epistemologically  as the amount of evidence needed to form a belief. Despite the criticism, his attitude towards the U&N theory is quite relaxed. According to Weatherson, the U&N theory can be used as a good heuristic for delivering the correct verdicts when doing applied semantics, i.e., when we try to determine the best meaning candidate for a particular predicate. In this paper, I try to show that the “good heuristic strategy” is of no use because A) there is no guarantee that the epistemological and the metaphysical criteria of naturalness deliver the same verdicts and B) even if they deliver the same verdicts, the difference in their theoretical backgrounds may affect arguments which rely on the verdicts. The difference will be shown by drawing on the example of Theodore Sider and his use of the U&N theory.

Year

Volume

27

Issue

1

Pages

85–104

Physical description

Dates

published
2018-03-15

Contributors

  • Department of Philosophy and Social Sciences, University of Hradec Králové, Hradec Králové, Czech Republic

References

  • Carnap, R., “Empiricism, semantics and ontology”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 2 (1950): 20–40.
  • Cziko, G., Without Miracles: Universal Selection Theory and the Second Darwinian Revolution, Cambridge MA, MIT Press, 1995.
  • Derksen, A., “Evolutionary epistemology in defense of the reliability of our everyday perceptual knowledge: A promise of evolutionary epistemology”, Philosophia-Naturalis, 38, 2 (2001): 245–270.
  • Goodman, N., Fact, Fiction and Forecast, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1955. Cited from: fourth edition, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1983.
  • Hirsch, E., “Language, ontology, and structure”, Noûs, 42, 3 (2008): 509–528. DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2008.00689.x
  • Hirsch, E., Quantifier Variance and Realism: Essays in Metaontology, New York, Oxford University Press, 2011.
  • Kripke, S., Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1982.
  • Lewis, D., Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1969.
  • Lewis, D., “Radical interpretation”, Synthese, 27, 3–4 (1974): 331–344. DOI: 10.1007/BF00484599
  • Lewis, D., “Languages and language”, pages 3–35 in K. Gunderson (ed.), Language, Mind, and Knowledge, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1975.
  • Lewis, D., “New Work for a Theory of Universals”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 4 (1983): 343–377. DOI: 10.1080/00048408312341131
  • Lewis, D., “Putnam’s Paradox”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 3 (1984): 221–236. DOI: 10.1080/00048408412340013
  • Lewis. D., “Mad Pain and Martian Pain”, pages 216–232 in N. Block (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1980.
  • Lewis, D., “Meaning without use: Reply to Hawthorne”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 1 (1992): 106–110. DOI: 10.1080/00048408112340093
  • Lewis, D., “Reduction of mind”, 412–431 in: S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Oxford, Blackwell, 1994.
  • Popper, K., “Evolutionary Epistemology”, in J.W. Pollard (ed.), Evolutionary Theory: Paths into the Future, London, John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 1984.
  • Putnam, H., Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
  • Quine, W., Word and Object, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1960.
  • Schwarz, W., “Against Magnetism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 1 (2014): 17–36. DOI: 10.1080/00048402.2013.765900
  • Sider, T., “Criteria of personal identity and the limits of conceptual analysis”, Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 1 (2001): 189–209. DOI: 10.1111/0029-4624.35.s15.10
  • Sider, T., Four-Dimensionalism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2001.
  • Sider, T., “Ontological Realism”, pages 384–423 in D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
  • Sider, T., “Sparseness, immanence, and naturalness”, Noûs, 29, 3 (1995): 360–377. DOI: 10.2307/2215604
  • Sider, T., Writing the Book of the World, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011.
  • Sperber, D., Wilson, D., Relevance: Communication and Cognition, Second Edition, Oxford/Cambridge, Blackwell Publishers, 1995.
  • Stalnaker, R., “Lewis on intentionality”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 1 (2004): 199–212. DOI: 10.1080/713659796
  • Stich, S., The Fragmentation of Reason: Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation, Cambridge MA, MIT Press, 1990.
  • Weatherson, B., “What Good are Counterexamples?”, Philosophical Studies, 115, 1 (2003): 1–31. DOI: 10.1023/A:1024961917413
  • Weatherson, B., “The role of naturalness in Lewis’s theory of meaning”, Journal for the History of Analytic Philosophy, 1, 1 (2013): 1–19. DOI: 10.4148/jhap.v1i10.1620
  • Williams, J.R.G., “Eligibility and inscrutability”, Philosophical Review, 116, 3 (2007): 361–399. DOI: 10.1215/00318108-2007-002
  • Williams, J.R.G., “Lewis on reference and eligibility”, pages 367–381 in B. Loewer and J. Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, Oxford, Wiley-Blackwell, 2015.
  • Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, Blackwell, 1953.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.desklight-524e9b48-a901-4041-b83a-09795abdbeee
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.