Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2018 | 27 | 2 | 151-160

Article title

Plantinga’s Haecceitism and Simple Quantified Modal Logic

Authors

Content

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

In a series of papers Alvin Plantinga argued for a serious actualist modal semantics based on the notions of possible world, understood as maximal possible state of affairs, and of individual essence (haecceity). Plantinga’s actualism is known as haecceitism. In spite of the fact that haecceitism has been thought by Plantinga to require a Kripke-style semantics, the aim of this paper is to show that it is compatible with constant domains semantics and the simplest quantified modal logic. I will argue that not only does this approach have all the advantages of a greater simplicity in combining quantification and modalities, but also it better conforms to the actualist program.

Year

Volume

27

Issue

2

Pages

151-160

Physical description

Dates

published
2018-06-15

Contributors

author
  • Department of Humanities University of Palermo 90128 Palermo, Italy

References

  • Adams, R.M., “Primitive thisness and primitive identity”, The Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979): 5–26. DOI: 10.2307/2025812
  • Bennett, K., “Proxy ‘actualism’”, Philosophical Studies 129 (2006): 263–294. DOI: 10.1007/s11098-004-1641-2
  • Hodes, H., “Axioms for actuality”, Journal of Philosophical Logic 13, 1 (1984): 27–34. DOI: 10.1007/BF00297575
  • Jager, T., “An actualist semantics for quantified modal logic”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (1982): 335–349.
  • Kripke, S., “Semantical considerations on modal logic”, Acta Philosophica Fennica 16 (1963): 83–94. Reprinted in J.-Y. Beziau (ed.), Universal Logic: An Anthology, pages 197–208, 2012. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-0346-0145-0_16
  • Linsky, B., and E. Zalta, “In defence of the simplest quantified modal logic”, Philosophical Perspectives 8, Logic and Language (1994): 431–458. DOI: 10.2307/2214181
  • Linsky, B., E. Zalta, “In defence of the contingently nonconcrete”, Philosophical Studies 84 (1996): 283–294. DOI: 10.1007/BF00354491
  • Menzel, C., “Actualism, ontological commitment, and possible worlds semantics”, Synthese 85, 3 (1990): 355–389. DOI: 10.1007/BF00484834
  • Nelson, M., E. Zalta, “Bennett and ‘proxy actualism’”, Philosophical Studies 142 (2009): 277–292. DOI: 10.1007/s11098-007-9186-9
  • Plantinga, A., “Actualism and possible worlds”, Theoria 42 (1976): 139–160. DOI: 10.1111/j.1755-2567.1976.tb00681.x
  • Plantinga, A., “On existentialism”, Philosophical Studies 44, 1 (1983): 1–20. DOI: 10.1007/BF00353411
  • Plantinga, A., “De essentia”, pages 139–157 in A. Plantinga and M. Davidson (eds.), Essays in the Metaphysics of Modality, Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York, 2003. DOI: 10.1093/0195103769.003.0008
  • Pollock, J.L., “Plantinga on possible worlds”, pages 121–144 in J.E. Tomberlin and P. van Inwagen (eds.), Alvin Plantinga, Profiles, Volume 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, Lancaster, 1985. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-009-5223-2_3
  • Quine, W.V.O., “On what there is”, in W.V.O. Quine From a Logical Point of View, Harvard U.P., Cambridge, Mass., 1953.
  • Williamson, T., “Existence and contingency”, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73, 1 (1999): 181–203. DOI: 10.1111/1467-8349.00054

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.desklight-a1dec48c-facf-4d6b-bf0a-1ce9f5f0d31b
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.