Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2015 | 41 | 1 | 9-23

Article title

Against Smallism And Localism

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
The question whether cognition ever extends beyond the head is widely considered to be an empirical issue. And yet, all the evidence amassed in recent years has not sufficed to settle the debate. In this paper we suggest that this is because the debate is not really an empirical one, but rather a matter of definition. Traditional cognitive science can be identified as wedded to the ideals of “smallism” and “localism”. We criticize these ideals and articulate a case in favor of extended cognition by highlighting the historical pedigree and conceptual adequacy of related empirical and theoretical work.

Publisher

Year

Volume

41

Issue

1

Pages

9-23

Physical description

Dates

published
2015-06-01
online
2015-07-24

Contributors

  • University of Cincinnati, USA
  • University of Cincinnati, USA

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43–64.[Crossref]
  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), Cambridge handbook on situated cognition (pp. 78–95). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Adolph, K. E. (2008). Learning to move. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17, 213–218.[Crossref][WoS]
  • Bak, P., Tang, C., & Wiesenfeld, K. (1988). Self-organized criticality. Physical Review A, 38, 364–374.
  • Bechtel, W., Abrahamsen, A., & Graham, G. (1999). The life of cognitive science. In W. Bechtel & G. Graham (Eds.), A companion to cognitive science. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Bhalla, M., & Proffitt, D. R. (1999). Visual-motor recalibration in geographical slant perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 25, 1076–1096.[Crossref]
  • Bongers, R. M., Michaels, C. F., & Smitsman, A. W. (2004). Variations of tool and task characteristics reveal that tool-user postures are anticipated. Journal of Motor Behavior, 36, 305–315.[Crossref]
  • Burton, G. (1992). Nonvisual judgment of the crossability of path gaps. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18, 698–713.[Crossref]
  • Burton, G. (1993). Non-neural extensions of haptic sensitivity. Ecological Psychology, 5, 105–124.[Crossref]
  • Cardinali, L., Frassinetti, F., Brozzoli, C., Urquizar, C., Roy, A. C., & Farne, A. (2009). Tool-use induces morphological updating of the body schema. Current Biology, 19, R478–R479.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). Defending extended cognition. In V. Sloutsky, B. Love, & K. McRae (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 129–134). New York: Psychology Press.
  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science. Review of General Psychology, 17, 145–150.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.[Crossref][WoS]
  • Dotov, D., & Chemero, A. (2014). Breaking the perception–action cycle: Experimental phenomenology of non-sense and its implications for theories of perception and movement science. In M. Cappuccio & T. Froese (Eds.), Enactive cognition at the edge of sense-making: Making sense of nonsense (pp. 37–60). Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Favela, L., & Chemero, A. (2014). The animal-environment system. In Y. Coello & M. Fischer (Eds.), Foundations of embodied cognition. Psychology Press, forthcoming.
  • Fitzpatrick, P., Carello, C., & Turvey, M. T. (1994). Eigenvalues of the inertia tensor and exteroception by the “muscular sense”. Neuroscience, 60, 551–568.[Crossref][PubMed]
  • Freeman, W. (2001). How brains make up their minds. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Gallagher, S. (2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 4–12.[WoS]
  • Gallagher, S. (2011). The overextended mind. Versus: Quaderni di studi semiotici, 113–115, 55–66.
  • Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Ishak, S., Adolph, K. E., & Lin, G. C. (2008). Perceiving affordances for fitting through apertures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance, 34, 1501–1514.[Crossref][WoS]
  • Jagacinski, R. J., & Flach, J. M. (2003). Control theory for humans: Quantitative approaches to modeling performance. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Retrieved from
  • Kugler, P. N., Kelso, J. A. S., & Turvey, M. T. (1980). Coordinative structures as dissipative structures I. Theoretical lines of convergence. In G. E. Stelmach & J. Requin (Eds.), Tutorials in motor behavior (pp. 3–47). Amsterdam: North-Holland.
  • Malek, E. A., & Wagman, J. B. (2008). Kinetic potential influences visual and remote haptic perception of affordances. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 61, 1813–1826.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Proffitt, D. R. (2006). Embodied perception and the economy of action. Perspectives in Psychological Science, 1, 110–122.
  • Regia-Corte, T., & Wagman, J. B. (2008). Perception of affordances for standing on an inclined surface depends on height of centre of mass. Experimental Brain Research, 191, 25–35.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.
  • Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Slaby, J., & Gallagher, S. (2015). Critical neuroscience and socially extended minds. Theory, Culture & Society, 32(1), 33–59.[WoS]
  • Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., Keil, P. G., & Barnier, A. J. (2010). The psychology of memory, extended cognition, and socially distributed remembering. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 521–560. doi: 10.1007/sll097-010-9182-y[Crossref][WoS]
  • Van Orden, G., Holden, J., & Turvey, M. T. (2003). Self-organization of cognitive performance. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 132, 331–351.[Crossref]
  • Wagman, J. B., & Taylor, K. R. (2004). Chosen-striking location and the user–tool–environment system. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 10, 267–280.[Crossref]
  • Wagman, J. B., & Taylor, K. R. (2005a). Perceiving affordances for aperture crossing for the person-plus-object system. Ecological Psychology, 17, 105–130.[Crossref]
  • Wagman, J. B., & Taylor, K. R. (2005b). Perceived arm posture and remote haptic perception of whether an object can be stepped over. Journal of Motor Behavior, 37, 339–342.[Crossref]
  • Warren, W. H., & Whang, S. (1987). Visual guidance of walking through apertures: Body-scaled information for affordances. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 371–383.[Crossref][WoS]
  • Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wilson, R., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.doi-10_1515_slgr-2015-0017
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.