Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2015 | 41 | 1 | 73-88

Article title

The Hard Problem Of Content: Solved (Long Ago)

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
In this paper, I argue that even if the Hard Problem of Content, as identified by Hutto and Myin, is important, it was already solved in naturalized semantics, and satisfactory solutions to the problem do not rely merely on the notion of information as covariance. I point out that Hutto and Myin have double standards for linguistic and mental representation, which leads to a peculiar inconsistency. Were they to apply the same standards to basic and linguistic minds, they would either have to embrace representationalism or turn to semantic nihilism, which is, as I argue, an unstable and unattractive position. Hence, I conclude, their book does not offer an alternative to representationalism. At the same time, it reminds us that representational talk in cognitive science cannot be taken for granted and that information is different from mental representation. Although this claim is not new, Hutto and Myin defend it forcefully and elegantly.

Publisher

Year

Volume

41

Issue

1

Pages

73-88

Physical description

Dates

published
2015-06-01
online
2015-07-24

Contributors

  • Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, Polish Academy of Sciences

References

  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 21(1), 7–19.
  • Bickhard, M. H. (1993). Representational content in humans and machines. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 5(4), 285–333. doi:10.1080/09528139308953775[Crossref]
  • Bickhard, M. H. (2008). The interactivist model. Synthese, 166(3), 547–591. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9375-x[WoS][Crossref]
  • Bickhard, M. H., & Richie, D. M. (1983). On the nature of representation: a case study of James Gibson’s theory of perception. New York: Praeger.
  • Bielecka, K. (2014). Błędne reprezentacje a pojęcie funkcji w teleosemantyce. Analiza koncepcji Dretskego i Millikan. Filozofia Nauki, 1(85), 105–120.
  • Brentano, F. (1900). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Hamburg: F. Meiner.
  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Campbell, R. J. (2011). The concept of truth. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Carroll, L. (1900). Alice’s adventures in wonderland. New York: Street & Smith.
  • Chrudzimski, A. (1999). Die Theorie der Intentionalität bei Franz Brentano. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 57, 45–66. doi:10.5840/gps1999574[Crossref]
  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431. doi:10.1007/BF01063896[Crossref]
  • Craik, K. (1967). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cummins, R., & Roth, M. (2012). Meaning and content in cognitive science. In R. Schantz (Ed.), Prospects for meaning (pp. 365–382). Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2010). Similarity after Goodman. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(1), 61–75. doi:10.1007/s13164-010-0035-y[Crossref]
  • Dretske, F. I. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief: form, content, and function (pp. 17–37). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Dretske, F. I. (1988). Explaining behaviour: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Field, H. (1972). Tarski’s theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 69(13), 347–375.
  • Fodor, J. A. (1992). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2015). Minds without meanings: An essay on the content of concepts.
  • Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting and knowing (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
  • Goodman, N. (1951). The structure of appearance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Harvey, M. I. (2015). Content in languaging: why radical enactivism is incompatible with representational theories of language. Language Sciences, 48, 90–129. doi:10.1016/j.langsci.2014.12.004[Crossref][WoS]
  • Hempel, C., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.[Crossref]
  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2011). Anti-representationalism: Not a well-founded theory of cognition. Res Cogitans, 2, 1–34.
  • MacKay, D. M. (1969). Information, mechanism and meaning. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Mendelovici, A. (2012). Reliable misrepresentation and tracking theories of mental representation. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 421–443. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-9966-8[WoS][Crossref]
  • Millikan, R. G. (1986). Thoughts without laws; cognitive science with content. The Philosophical Review, 95(1), 47–80.
  • Millikan, R. G. (2007). An input condition for teleosemantics? Reply to Shea (and Godfrey-Smith). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 436–455. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2007.00083.x[Crossref]
  • Miłkowski, M. (2015a). Function and causal relevance of content. New Ideas in Psychology, 1–9. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2014.12.003[Crossref]
  • Miłkowski, M. (2015b). Satisfaction conditions in anticipatory mechanisms. Biology & Philosophy, (February). doi:10.1007/s10539-015-9481-3[Crossref]
  • Newman, M. H. A. (1928). Mr. Russell’s “Causal Theory of Perception”. Mind, 37(146), 137–148.
  • Pattee, H. H. (1972). Physical problems of decision-making constraints. International Journal of Neuroscience, 3(3), 99–105. doi:10.3109/00207457209147629[Crossref]
  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511597954[Crossref]
  • Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sloman, A. (2010). What’s information, for an organism or intelligent machine? How can a machine or organism mean? In G. Dodig-Crnkovic & M. Burgin (Eds.), Information and computation. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.
  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449–508.[Crossref]
  • Tarski, A. (1933). Pojecie prawdy w jezykach nauk dedukcyjnych. Prace Towarzystwa Naukowego Warszawskiego, Wydzial III Nauk Matematyczno-Fizycznych, (34).
  • Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychologial Review, 84(4), 327–352.
  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • White, M., & Tarski, A. (1987). A philosophical letter of Alfred Tarski. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(1), 28–32.
  • Woodward, J. (2001). Law and explanation in biology: Invariance is the kind of stability that matters. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 1–20.[Crossref]

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.doi-10_1515_slgr-2015-0021
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.