Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


Journal

2013 | 23 | 4 | 606-615

Article title

Reconsidering philosophical questions and neuroscientific answers: Two pillars of inquiry

Authors

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
I propose the next steps in the neuropragmatic approach to philosophy that has been advocated by Solymosi and Shook (2013). My focus is the initial process of inquiry implicit in addressing philosophical questions of cognition and mind by utilizing the tools of neuroscientific research. I combine John Dewey’s pattern of inquiry with Charles Peirce’s three forms of inference in order to outline a methodological schema for neuropragmatic inquiry. My goal is to establish ignorance and guessing as well-defined pillars of methodology upon which to build a neuropragmatic approach to inquiry. First, I outline Dewey’s pattern of inquiry, highlighting the initial problematic phase in which recognized ignorance provides the basis upon which to frame a philosophical problem and initiate the trajectory by which philosophical questions may be addressed with the assistance of neuroscientific evidence. Second, I provide an outline of Peirce’s three forms of inference, focusing upon the first phase of abduction: guessing. Third, I explain the transition between ignorance and guessing, urging the benefit of attending to these two aspects of inquiry. Finally, I provide an initial sketch indicating the next steps concerning a pragmatic reconstruction of neurophilosophy, pointing towards the need for a more thorough examination of scientific methodology within and following analyses of philosophical problems and neuroscientific evidence.

Publisher

Journal

Year

Volume

23

Issue

4

Pages

606-615

Physical description

Dates

published
2013-10-01
online
2013-09-28

Contributors

author
  • Prairie View A&M University

References

  • [1] Anderson, D. (1986). The Evolution of Peirce’s Concept of Abduction. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 26(2), 145–164.
  • [2] Anderson, D. (1987). Creativity and the Philosophy of C.S. Peirce. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7760-1[Crossref]
  • [3] Anderson, D. (2005). The Esthetic Attitude of Abduction. Semiotica 153(1), 9–22.
  • [4] Brown, M. (2012). John Dewey’s Logic of Science. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 2(2), 258–306. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/666843[Crossref]
  • [5] Burke, T. (1994). Dewey’s New Logic: A Reply to Russell. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • [6] Churchland, P.M. (2012). Plato’s Camera: How the Physical Brain Captures a Landscape of Abstract Universals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • [7] Churchland, P.S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • [8] Churchland, P.S. (2002). Brainwise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • [9] Curd, M. (1980). The Logic of Discovery: An Analysis of Three Approaches. In T. Nickles (Ed.). Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, pp. 201–219. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8986-3_8[Crossref]
  • [10] Firestein, Suart. (2012). Ignorance: How It Drives Science. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • [11] Gazzaniga, M. (1992). Nature’s Mind: The Biological Roots of Thinking, Emotion, Sexuality, Language, and Intelligence. New York: Basic Books.
  • [12] Harris, S. (2011). The Moral Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values. New York: The Free Press.
  • [13] Hintikka, J. (1989). Questioning as a Philosophical Method. The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic: Selected Essays, pp. 215–233. Norwell, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2647-9_14[Crossref]
  • [14] Laudan, L. (1980). Why was the Logic of Discovery Abandoned? In T. Nickles (Ed.). Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, pp. 173–183. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8986-3_6[Crossref]
  • [15] Nickles, T. (2009). The Strange Story of Scientific Method. In J. Meheus and T. Nickles (Eds.). Models of Discovery and Creativity, pp. 167–207. Dordrecht: Springer Science + Business Media. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3421-2_9[Crossref]
  • [16] Nubiola, J. (2005). Abduction or the Logic of Surprise. Semiotica 153(1), 117–130.
  • [17] Popper, K. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books.
  • [18] Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11656-000[Crossref]
  • [19] Reichenbach, H. (1951). The Rise of Scientific Philosophy. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  • [20] Santaella, L. (2005). Abduction: The Logic of Guessing. Semiotica 153(1), 175–198.
  • [21] Schulkin, J. (2011). Social Allostasis: Anticipatory Regulation of the Internal Milieu. Frontiers in Evolutionary Neuroscience 2, 1–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnevo.2010.00111[Crossref]
  • [22] Solymosi, T. (2011a). Neuropragmatism, Old and New. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10(3), 347–368. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9202-6[Crossref]
  • [23] Solymosi, T. (2011b). A Reconstruction of Freedom in the Age of Neuroscience: A View from Neuropragmatism. Contemporary Pragmatism 8(1), 153–171.
  • [24] Solymosi, T. (2012). Pragmatism, Inquiry, and Design: A Dynamic Approach. In R. Gordon, L. Stillwaggon Swan, and J. Seckbach (Eds.). Origin(s) of Design in Nature: A Fresh, Interdisciplinary Look at How Design Emerges in Complex Systems, Especially Life, pp. 143–160. Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.
  • [25] Solymosi, T. and Shook, J. (2013). Neuropragmatism: A Neurophilosophical Manifesto. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 5(1), 212–234.
  • [26] Solymosi, T. and Shook, J. (forthcoming). Neuropragmatism and the Culture of Inquiry: Moving Beyond Creeping Cartesianism. Intellectica: The Journal of the French Association for Cognitive Research.
  • [27] Thagard, P. (1978). The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice. The Journal of Philosophy 75(2), 76–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2025686[Crossref]
  • [28] Ylikoski, P. and Kuorikoski, J. (2010). Dissecting Explanatory Power. Philosophical Studies 148, 201–219. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9324-z[Crossref][WoS]

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.doi-10_2478_s13374-013-0152-2
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.