Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2014 | 36 | 1 | 121-142

Article title

From Speech Acts to Semantics

Authors

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
Frege introduced the notion of pragmatic force as what distinguishes statements from questions. This distinction was elaborated by Wittgenstein in his later works, and systematised as an account of different kinds of speech acts in formal dialogue theory by Hamblin. It lies at the heart of the inferential semantics more recently developed by Brandom. The present paper attempts to sketch some of the relations between these developments.

Publisher

Year

Volume

36

Issue

1

Pages

121-142

Physical description

Dates

published
2014-03-01
online
2014-04-12

Contributors

author
  • University of Sydney

References

  • Æsop. (Fab.). Fables, tr. S.A. Handford, 1954. Repr. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1966.
  • Anderson, A.R., & Belnap, N.D. Jr. (1975). Entailment: the logic of relevance and necessity, vol. 1. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
  • Anderson, A.R., Belnap, N.D. Jr., & Dunn, J.M. (1992). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity, vol. 2. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
  • Appel, R. (1995). Mother Simpson. Episode of Groening, M., The Simpsons (Fox Television Series), season 7, episode 8, code 3F06, first broadcast 19 Novem- ber 1995.
  • Aristotle. (An.Prior.). Prior analytics, tr. A.J. Jenkinson. In Aristotle, Works ed. W.D. Ross, vol. 1. London: Oxford University Press, 1928. References by book and chapter, and by the Bekker pagination.
  • Aristotle. (Soph.El.). Sophistical refutations, tr. W.A. Pickard-Cambridge. In Aris- totle, Works, ed. W.D. Ross, vol. 1 (London: Oxford University Press, 1928). References by chapter, and by the Bekker pagination.
  • Black, M. (1985). The prevalence of humbug. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
  • Brandom, R.B. (1981). Leibniz and degrees of perception. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 19 (4), 447-449.
  • Brandom, R.B. (1994). Making it explicit: reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
  • Brandom, R.B. (2008). Between saying and doing: towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Budzynska, K., & Witek, M. (2014). Non-inferential aspects of Ad Hominem and Ad Baculum. In K. Budzynska & M. Koszowy (Eds.), Polish School of Argumentation, special issue of the journal Argumentation, vol. 3 (in press).
  • Carroll, L. (Charles Dodgson). (1871). Through the looking-glass, and what Alice found there. Repr. with notes in The annotated Alice, ed. M. Gardiner. Har- mondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1965.
  • Carroll, L. (Charles Dodgson). (1895). What the Tortoise said to Achilles. Mind, n.s. 4, 278-80. 139
  • Davidson, D. (1975). Thought and talk. In his Inquiries into truth and interpretation. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984, pp. 155-170.
  • Deleuze, G. (1990). The logic of sense, tr. M. Lester. Repr. London: Continuum, 2004.
  • Descartes, R. (1641). Meditations on first philosophy, in Descartes, Philosophical writings, tr. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff & D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press, 1984, vol. 2, pp. 3-62.
  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: philosophy of language. London: Gerald Duckworth.
  • Fine, K. (1974). Models for entailment. Journal of Philosophical Logic 3, 347-372.
  • Frankfurt, H.G. (2005). On bullshit. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, tr. S. Bauer-Mengelberg, in From Frege to G¨odel: a source book in mathematical logic, 1879-1931, ed. J. van Heijenoort. Cam- bridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1967, 1981, pp. 1-82.
  • Frege, G. (1881). Boole’s logical calculus and the concept script. In his Posthumous writings, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel & F. Kaulbach, tr. P. Long & R. White. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 9-46.
  • Frege, G. (1884). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, tr. J.L. Austin as The foundations of arithmetic, 2nd edn revd. Oxford: Blackwell, 1955.
  • Frege, G. (1903). Appendix to his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet (Jena: H. Pohle), vol. 2; tr. in his The basic laws of arithmetic ed. and tr. M. Furth. Berkeley, California: University of California Press, 1967, pp. 127-143.
  • Frege, G. (1918). Thought. Tr. in The Frege reader, ed. M. Beaney. Oxford: Black- well, 1997, pp. 325-345.
  • Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.
  • Hamblin, C.L. (1971). Mathematical models of dialogue. Theoria 37, 130-155.
  • Hamblin, C.L. (1979). Logic in application: lecture notes 1979. Kensington, N.S.W.: School of Philosophy, University of New South Wales.
  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Being and time; Sein und Zeit, tr. J. Macquarie & E. Robin- son, from the 8th German edition of 1957. New York: Harper and Row, 1962.
  • Hofstadter, D.R. (1979). G¨odel, Escher, Bach: An eternal golden braid. Hassocks, Sussex: Harvester.
  • Homer. (Il.). The Iliad, with tr. by A.T. Murray. London, William Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library 1924.
  • Indrzejczak, A. (1998). Jaśkowski and Gentzen approaches to natural deduction and related systems. In K. Kijania-Placek & J. Woleński, The Lvov-Warsaw school and contemporary philosophy (pp. 253-264). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Kacprzak, M., & Yaskorska, O. (2014). Dialogue protocols for formal fallacies. In K. Budzynska & M. Koszowy (Eds.), Polish School of Argumentation, special issue of the journal Argumentation, vol. 3 (in press). Kant, I. (1781/7) Critique of pure reason, tr. N. Kemp Smith, 1929, revd 1933. Repr. London: Macmillan, 1963. References according to the first (A) and second (B) German editions.
  • Leibniz, G.W. (1676). What is an idea? Tr. in Leibniz, Selections, ed. P. P. Wiener (New York: Charles Scribner’s sons, 1951), pp. 281-283 [= Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, ed. C.I. Gerhardt (Berlin, 1875-1890), vol. 7. pp. 263-264)].
  • Leibniz, G.W. (1686/7). Correspondence with Arnauld. Partly tr. in Leibniz, Philosophical writings, ed. G.H.R. Parkinson (London: J.M. Dent & Sons, 1973), pp. 48-74 [= Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, ed. C.I. Gerhardt (Berlin, 1875-1890), vol. 2, pp. 17 ff.]. References by the date of letter, and by page of the translation.
  • Leibniz, G.W. (1712). Metaphysical consequences of the principle of reason. Tr. in his Philosophical writings, ed. G.H.R. Parkinson (London: J.M. Dent & sons. 1973), pp. 172-178 [= Opuscules et fragments in´edits de Leibniz, ed. L. Couturat (Paris, 1903), pp. 11-16]. References by section, and by page of the translation.
  • Leibniz, G.W. (1765). New essays on human understanding, tr. P. Remnant & J. Bennett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, repr. 1993. Paginated as for the Berlin Academy 1962 edition.
  • Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning human understanding, ed. J.W. Yolton (Lon- don: J.M. Dent & sons, 1961).
  • Mackenzie, J. (1979). How to stop talking to tortoises. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20, 705-717.
  • Mackenzie, J. (1984). Frege and illogical behavior. American Philosophical Quarterly 21 (4), 339-348.
  • Mackenzie, J. (1988). Distinguo: the response to equivocation. Argumentation 2, 465-482.
  • Mackenzie, J. (1990). Four dialogue systems. Studia Logica 49, 567-583.
  • Meyer, R.K. (1975). Sugihara is a characteristic matrix for RM. § 29.3 of Anderson & Belnap (1975), pp. 393-420.
  • Portnoi, G. (2010). Why are you so fat?: the TalkSPORT book of cricket’s best ever sledges. London: Simon & Schuster.
  • Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: from if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Quine, W.V. (1951). The problem of meaning in linguistics. Repr. in his From a logical point of view, 2nd edn revd. New York: Harper & Row Torchbook, 1961, pp. 47-64.
  • Read, S. (1988). Relevant logic. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Remnant, P., & Bennett, J. (1981). Editors’ introduction, to their translation of G.W. Leibniz (1765), pp. xi-xxii. Routley, R., Meyer, R.K., Plumwood, V. & Brady, R. 1983: Relevant logics and their rivals. Atascardero, California: Ridgeview.
  • Rubin, H., & Rubin, J.E. (1985). Equivalents of the axiom of choice II. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
  • Russell, B. (1902). Letter to Frege, 16 June. Tr. B. Woodward, in From Frege to G¨odel: a source book in mathematical logic, 1879-1931, ed. J. van Heijenoort. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1967, 1981, pp. 124-5.
  • Sellars, W. (1975). Autobiographical reflections (February, 1973). In Action, knowledge, and reality: critical studies in honor of Wilfrid Sellars, ed. H.- N. Casta˜neda. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975, pp. 277-293.
  • Sextus Empiricus. (Pyrr.Hyp.). Outlines of Pyrrhonism. In his Works, with tr. by R.G. Bury. London: William Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library, 1933, vol. 1.
  • Shaw, G.B. (1924). Saint Joan: a chronicle play in six scenes and an epilogue. Repr. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1962.
  • Sokal, A., & Bricmont, J. (1998). Intellectual impostures. London: Profile.
  • Stevenson, R.L. (1883). Treasure island. Repr. New York: Grosset & Dunlap, 1981.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1921). Tractatus logico-philosophicus, with tr. by D.F. Pears & B.F. McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations, with tr. by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2nd edn 1958.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.doi-10_2478_slgr-2014-0006
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.