Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

Results found: 2

first rewind previous Page / 1 next fast forward last

Search results

help Sort By:

help Limit search:
first rewind previous Page / 1 next fast forward last
EN
This article attempts to develop ideas included in Stump and Gallagher's papers on St. Thomas Aquinas' understanding of love. Aquinas based his theory of disinterested love on the difference between 'amor amicitiae' and 'amor concupiscentiae'. It is easy to misunderstand this difference. St. Thomas holds that both 'amor amicitiae' and 'amor concupiscentiae' are two sides of the same coin, or two 'movements' inside one act of love, to use Aquinas' own terms. 'Amor amicitiae' is directed at the 'substance' of a person, to something hidden in the center of a person, which can hardly be grasped and which is the basis for all personal features. This kind of love, Aquinas says, expresses the human desire for union with the beloved. 'Amor concupiscentiae', on the other hand, is directed at something that may be termed 'goodness for the beloved'; it tries to gain values of various kinds for the beloved person. On Aquinas' view, then, each love has two main objects: 'goodness of the person' and 'goodness for the person'. St. Thomas' metaphysics of disinterested love begins with recognizing the coexistence of these two movements within an act of love. According to Aquinas, to love someone with disinterested love means treating that person as an 'other self' - alter ego. This is possible only through 'affective unity' with the beloved. In a condition of 'affective unity' the concept of 'bonum sui' or 'goodness for myself' widens extensively. 'Goodnes for myself' coincides with 'goodness for the beloved', because we have entered a union on the spiritual level. This spiritual union would not be possible without the human capacity for 'extasis' (ecstasy), which in the context of Aquinas' metaphysics of the person denotes a human capacity to exist 'outside oneself' (extra se). These are the fundamental characteristics of Aquinas' theory of love, and they allow him to examine other matters such as the role of intention in the act of love, goodness as a disposition (dispositio), and so on.
|
2016
|
vol. 64
|
issue 1
49-59
PL
W niniejszym tekście próbuję krytycznie przeanalizować artykuł Saula Smilansky’ego o modlitwie prośby z punktu widzenia filozofii i teologii tomistycznej. Najbardziej kontrowersyjne wydają mi się następujące elementy: 1. Odmowa zastosowania zasady podwójnego skutku do jednego z opisanych w artykule przypadków. Uważam, że ta odmowa jest zakorzeniona w wątpliwym rozumieniu prawa do obrony samego siebie; 2. Niedocenienie roli sprawiedliwej kary w rządach Opatrzności; 3. Nieznajomość albo niechęć do wprowadzenia pojęcia „dopustu Bożego”; 4. Nie do końca trafne psychologiczne spostrzeżenia dotyczące ludzki modlących się do Boga o pomoc w skrajnie trudnych okolicznościach. Najogólniej rzecz ujmując, większość problemów poruszana przez Smilansky’ego tylko akcydentalnie dotyczy zagadnienia sensowności modlitwy prośby. Powstanie tych problemów wiąże się raczej z takimi a nie innymi rozwiązaniami problemów moralnych niż z modlitwą prośby jako taką.
EN
This paper takes a Thomistic point of view to critically analyze several points of Saul Smilansky’s article on petitionary prayer. The most controversial aspects of Smilansky’s paper are as follows: 1. It seems that the author has some difficulties with the principle of double effect, because his understanding of the human right to self-defense is highly debatable. 2. The author fails to appreciate the role of just punishment. 3. Apparently, Smilansky doesn’t know or doesn’t accept the theology of God’s permission which narrows his view of the cases he discusses. 4. His psychological account of petitionary pray is far from convincing. Generally speaking, although the title cites petitionary prayer as its central problem, in fact the main controversies refer to moral questions which can be discussed without introducing the concept of God’s agency. In order to solve Smilansky’s paradoxes we should first answer these fundamental moral difficulties.
first rewind previous Page / 1 next fast forward last
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.