Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2018 | 27 | 4 Special Issue on Logic, Cognition, Argumentation. Guest Editors: Mariusz Urbański, Michiel van Lambalgen and Marcin Koszowy | 421-451

Article title

Logic, Reasoning, Argumentation: Insights from the Wild

Authors

Content

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
This article provides a brief selective overview and discussion of recent research into natural language argumentation that may inform the study of human reasoning on the assumption that an episode of argumentation issues an invitation to accept a corresponding inference. As this research shows, arguers typically seek to establish new consequences based on prior information. And they typically do so vis-à-vis a real or an imagined opponent, or an opponent-position, in ways that remain sensitive to considerations of context, audiences, and goals. Deductively valid inferences remain a limiting case of such reasoning. In view of these insights, it may appear less surprising that allegedly “irrational” behavior can regularly be produced in experimental settings that expose subjects to standardized reasoning tasks.

Keywords

Contributors

author
  • Philosophy & Cognitive Science, Lund University Box 192, 22100 Lund, Sweden
  • Konstanz University, Philosophy Box D9, 78457 Konstanz, Germany
  • SAS, Institute of Philosophy Klemensova 19, 81364 Bratislava, Slovakia

References

  • Aberdein, A., and I.J. Dove, (issue eds.), 2009, Foundations of Science (Mathematical argumentation) 14, 1–2: 1–152.
  • Alexy, R., 2003, “On balancing and subsumption. A structural comparison”, Ratio Juris 16, 4: 433–449. DOI: 10.1046/j.0952-1917.2003.00244.x
  • Apel, K.-O., 1975, “The problem of philosophical fundamental-grounding in light of a transcendental pragmatic of language”, Man and World 8, 3: 239–275. DOI: 10.1007/BF01255646
  • Barth, E.M., and E.C.W. Krabbe, 1982, From Axiom to Dialogue. A Philosophical Study of Logics and Argumentation, Berlin/New York, NY: de Gruyter.
  • Betz, G., 2012, Debate dynamics: How controversy improves our beliefs, Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-007-4599-5
  • Blair, J.A., 2011, “Informal logic and its early historical development” Studies in Logic 4, 1: 1–16.
  • Burgess, J.P., 2008, “Tarski’s tort”, pages 149–168 in J.P. Burgess, Mathematics, Models, and Modality: Selected Philosophical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511487347.010
  • Burgess, J.P., 2011, “Kripke models”, pages 119–140 in Berger, A. (ed.), Saul Kripke, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511780622.006
  • Cohen, L.J., 1981, “Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 317–370. DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X00009092
  • Conley, T.M., 1990, Rhetoric in the European Tradition, Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
  • Dow, J., 2015, Passions and Persuasion in Aristotle’s Rhetoric, Oxford: Oxford University Pressm. DOI: 9780198716266.001.0001
  • Ehrensberger, J., and C. Zinn, 2011, “DIALOG. A system for dialogical logic”, manuscript. http://www.ccs.neu.edu/home/lieber/courses/se-courses/cs5500/sp11/lectures/Ehrensberger-Zinn-DiaLog.pdf (accessed 15 Nov 2012)
  • Evans, J.S.T.B., 2002, “Logic and human reasoning: An assessment of the deduction paradigm”, Psychological Bulletin 128, 6: 978–996. DOI: 10.1037/0033-2909.128.6.978
  • Evans, J.S.B.T., 2008, “Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition”, Annual Review of Psychology 59, 1: 255–278. DOI: 10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629
  • Frankish, K., and J.S.B.T. Evans, 2009, “The duality of mind: an historical perspective”, pages 1–29 in J.S.B.T. Evans and K. Frankish (eds.), In two Minds: Dual Processes and Beyond, Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199230167.003.0001
  • Floridi, L., 2009, “Logical fallacies as informational shortcuts”, Synthese 167, 2: 317–325. DOI: 10.1007/s11229-008-9410-y
  • Gabbay, D.M., R.H. Johnson, H.J. Ohlbach, and J. Woods (eds.), 2002, Handbook of the Logic of Argument and Inference: The Turn towards the Practical, Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • Gabbay, D.M., and J. Woods, 2002, “Formal approaches to practical reasoning: a survey”, pages 450–481 in [Gabbay et al., 2002]. DOI: 10.1016/S1570-2464(02)80013-1
  • Gigerenzer, G., and T. Sturm, 2012, “How (far) can rationality be naturalized?”, Synthese 187: 243–268. DOI: 10.1007/s11229-011-0030-6
  • Gigerenzer, G., P.M. Todd, and ABC Research Group, 1999, Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart, New York, NY/Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
  • Godden, D.M., and F. Zenker, 2015, “Denying antecedents and affirming consequents: The state of the art”, Informal Logic 35, 1: 88–134. DOI: 10.22329/il.v35i1.4173
  • Godden, D.M., and F. Zenker, 2016, “A probabilistic analysis of argument cogency” Synthese (forthcoming). DOI: 10.1007/s11229-016-1299-2
  • Goodnight, G.T., 2006, “Complex cases and legitimation inference: Extending the Toulmin model to legitimation argument in controversy”, pages 39–48 in D. Hitchcock and B. Verheij (eds.), Arguing on the Toulmin Model. New Essays in Argument Analysis and Evaluation, Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: 10.1007/978-1-4020-4938-5
  • Groarke, L., 2016, “Informal logic”, in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/logic-informal/
  • Habermas, J., 1996, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy [W. Rehg (transl.)], Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • Hahn, U., and A.J.L. Harris, 2014, “What does it mean to be biased: Motivated reasoning and rationality”, Psychology of Learning and Motivation 61:41–102. DOI: 10.1016/B978-0-12-800283-4.00002-2
  • Hahn, U., and J. Hornikx, 2016, “A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation”, Synthese 193, 6: 1833–1873. DOI: 10.1007/s11229-015-0815-0
  • Hahn, U., and M. Oaksford, 2006a, “A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies”, Synthese 152, 2: 207–236. DOI: 10.1007/s11229-005-5233-2
  • Hahn, U., and M. Oaksford, 2006b, “A normative theory of argument strength”, Informal Logic 26: 1–24. DOI: 10.22329/il.v26i1.428
  • Hamby, B., 2012, “Toulmin’s ‘Analytic Arguments’”; Informal Logic 32, 1: 116–131. DOI: 10.22329/il.v32i1.3099
  • Hansen, H.V., 2002, “The straw thing of fallacy theory: The standard definition of ‘fallacy’”, Argumentation 16: 133–155.
  • Harris, A.J.L., U. Hahn, J.K. Madsen, and A.S. Hsu, 2016, “The appeal to expert opinion: Quantitative support for a Bayesian network”, Approaches to Cognitive Science 40, 6: 1496–1533. DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12276
  • Hamblin, C.L., 1970, Fallacies, London: Methuen.
  • Harrah, D., 1987, “Hintikka’s theory of questions”, paged 199–213 in R. Bogdan (ed.), Jaakko Hintikka, Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-009-3763-5_8
  • Hertwig, R., A. Ortmann, and G. Gigerenzer, 1997, “Deductive competence: A desert devoid of content and context”, Current Psychology of Cognition 16: 102–107.
  • Henrich, J., S. Heine, and A. Norenzayan, 2010, “The weirdest people in the world?”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33, 2–3: 61–135. DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X0999152X
  • Hintikka, J.J., and P.V. Spade, 2012, “History of logic”, Encyclopedia Britannica. http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/346217/history-of-logic (accessed 20 Nov 2012)
  • Hofstede, G., 2001, Culture’s Consequences: Comparing Values, Behaviours, Institutions and Organizations Across Nations (2 nd edition). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
  • Jacot, J., E. Genot, and F. Zenker, 2016, “From reasonable preferences, via argumentation, to logic”, Journal of Applied Logic 18: 105–128. DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.08.001
  • Johnson, R.H., 2006, “Making sense of informal logic”, Informal Logic 26, 3: 231–258. DOI: 10.22329/il.v26i3.453
  • Johnson, R.H., 2011, “Informal logic and deductivism”, Studies in Logic 4, 1: 17—37.
  • Kahneman, D., 2011, Thinking, Fast and Slow, New York, NY: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.
  • Korb, K., 2004, “Bayesian informal logic and fallacy”, Informal Logic, 23, 2: 41–70. DOI: 10.22329/il.v24i1.2132
  • Lakatos, I., 2015 (1976), Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical Discovery, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781316286425 and 10.1017/CBO9781139171472
  • Lorenz, K., and P. Lorenzen, 1978, Dialogische Logik Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
  • Mercier, H., and D. Sperber, 2011, “Why do humans reason. Arguments for an argumentative theory”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34, 2: 57–111. DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X10000968
  • Meyer, M., 2010, “The Brussels school of rhetoric: From the new rhetoric to problematology”, Philosophy and Rhetoric 43, 4: 403–429.
  • Oaksford, M., and N. Chater, 1991, “Against logicist cognitive science”, Mind & Language 6: 1–38. DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.1991.tb00173.x
  • Perelman, C., and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1969 (1958), The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argument, [J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver (transl.)], Notre Dame, IN and London: University of Notre Dame Press. [French original: La Nouvelle Rhétorique: Traité de l’Argumentation, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1958.
  • Pietroski, P., 2015, “Logical form”, in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/logical-form
  • Pollock, J.L., 1987, “Defeasible reasoning”, Cognitive Science 11, 4: 481–518. DOI: 10.1207/s15516709cog1104_4
  • Pollock, J.L., 1995, Cognitive Carpentry: A Blueprint for How to Build a Person, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Reiter, R., 1980, “A logic for default reasoning”, Artificial Intelligence 13, 1–2: 81–132. DOI: 10.1016/0004-3702(80)90014-4
  • Schwartz, S.H., 1994, “Are there universal aspects in the content and structure of values?”, Journal of Social Issues 50, 4: 19-45. DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-4560.1994.tb01196.x
  • Schwartz, S.H., 2012, “An overview of the Schwartz theory of basic values”, Online Readings in Psychology and Culture 2, 1. DOI: 10.9707/2307-0919.1116
  • Schwartz, S.H., and A. Bardi, 2001, “Value hierarchies across cultures taking a similarities perspective”, Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 32, 3: 268–290.
  • Simon, H., 1948, Administrative Behaviour: A Study of the Decision Making Processes in Administrative Organisation, New York: Macmillan.
  • Simon, H.A., 1982, Models of Bounded Rationality, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Spade, P.V., and M. Yrjönsuuri, 2014, “Medieval theories of obligationes”, in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/obligationes
  • Spohn, W., 2002, “A brief comparison of Pollock’s defeasible reasoning and ranking functions”, Synthese 131, 1: 39–56. DOI: 10.1023/A:1015004212541
  • Spohn, W., 2012, The Laws of Belief: Ranking Functions and their Applications, Oxford: Oxford UP. DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697502.001.0001
  • Stanovich, K.E., 1999, Who is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning, Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
  • Stenning, K., and M. van Lambalgen, 2008, Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Strasser, C., and G.A. Antonelli, 2016, “Non-monotonic logic”, in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall Edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/logic-nonmonotonic
  • Tindale, C., 2004, Rhetorical Argumentation: Principles of Theory and Practice, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
  • Toulmin, S.E., 1958, The Uses of Argument, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511840005
  • Toulmin, S.E., 1992, “Rhetoric, and reason: Redressing the balance”, pages 3–11 in F.H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair, and C.A. Willards (eds), Argumentation Illuminated: Proceedings of the Second ISSA Conference on Argumentation, SicSat: Amsterdam.
  • van Bentham, J., 2009, “One Logician’s Perspective on Argumentation”, Cogency 1, 2: 13–25.
  • van Eemeren, F.H., 2010, Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse.
  • Extending the Pragma-Dialectical Theory of Argumentation, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: 10.1075/aic.2
  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst, 2004, A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The Pragma-Dialectical Approach, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511616389
  • van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, and F.S. Henkemans, 1996, Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments, Mawhah: Lawrence Erlbaum.
  • van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, and B. Meuffels, 2012, “Effectiveness through reasonableness: Preliminary steps to pragma-dialectical effectiveness research”, Argumentation 26: 33–53. DOI: 10.1007/s10503-011-9234-7
  • Verheij, B., 2009, “The Toulmin argument model in artificial intelligence. Or: how semi-formal, defeasible argumentation schemes creep into logic”, pages 219–238 in I. Rahwan and G. Simari (eds.), Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence, Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: 10.1007/978-0-387-98197-0_11
  • Walton, D.N., 1991, “Hamblin on the standard treatment of fallacies”, Philosophy and Rhetoric 24, 4: 353–361.
  • Walton, D.N., 1995, A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy, Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.
  • Walton, D.N., 2010, “Why fallacies appear to be better arguments than they are”, Informal Logic 30, 2: 159–184. DOI: 10.22329/il.v30i2.2868
  • Walton, D.N., and R.H. Johnson, 2011, “Editors’ introduction. Special issue on Charles Hamblin”, Informal Logic 31, 4: i–iv.
  • Walton, D.N., and E. Krabbe, 1995, Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
  • Walton, D.N., C. Reed, and F. Macagno, 2008, Argumentation Schemes, Cambridge University Press, New York. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511802034
  • Woods, J., R.H. Johnson, D.M. Gabbay, and H.J. Ohlbach, 2002, “Logic and the practical turn”, pages 1–39 in [Gabbay et al., 2002]. DOI: 10.1016/S1570-2464(02)80003-9
  • Zenker, F., 2011, “Experts and bias: When is the interest-based objection to an authority argument sound?”, Argumentation 25: 355–370. DOI: 10.1007/s10503-011-9226-7
  • Zenker, F., 2012, “The explanatory value of cognitive asymmetries in policy controversies”, pages 441–452 in J. Goodwin and R. Delaplante (eds.), Between Scientists and Citizens, Ames, IO: GPSA.
  • Zenker, F., 2013, “What do normative approaches to argumentation stand to gain from rhetorical insights?”, Philosophy & Rhetoric 46, 4: 415–436. DOI: 10.5325/philrhet.46.4.0415
  • Zenker, F., and C. Dahlman, 2016, “Reliable debiasing techniques in legal contexts? Weak signals from a darker corner of the social science universe”, pages 173–196 in F. Paglieri, L. Bonelli, and S. Felletti (eds.), The Psychology of Argument: Cognitive Approaches to Argumentation and Persuasion, London: College Publications.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.desklight-0fcb9815-03e9-4aab-bba1-e90ff8661ed2
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.