Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2015 | 40 | 1 | 63-90

Article title

Explaining Cognitive Phenomena with Internal Representations: A Mechanistic Perspective

Title variants

Languages of publication

EN

Abstracts

EN
Despite the fact that the notion of internal representation has - at least according to some - a fundamental role to play in the sciences of the mind, not only has its explanatory utility been under attack for a while now, but it also remains unclear what criteria should an explanation of a given cognitive phenomenon meet to count as a (truly, genuinely, nontrivially, etc.) representational explanation in the first place. The aim of this article is to propose a solution to this latter problem. I will assume that representational explanations should be construed as a form of mechanistic explanations and proceed by proposing a general sketch of a functional architecture of a representational cognitive mechanism. According to the view on offer here, representational mechanisms are mechanisms that meet four conditions: the structural resemblance condition, the action-guidance condition, the decouplability condition, and the error-detection condition.

Publisher

Year

Volume

40

Issue

1

Pages

63-90

Physical description

Dates

published
2015-03-01
online
2015-04-10

Contributors

  • Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, Polish Academy of Sciences

References

  • Anderson,M. L., & Rosenberg, G. (2008). Content and action: The guidance theory of representation. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 29, 55-86.
  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 55, 7-19.
  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.
  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: a mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421-441.
  • Bickhard, M. H. (1999). Interaction and representation. Theory and Psychology, 9, 435-458.[Crossref]
  • Bickhard, M. H. (2004). The dynamic emergence of representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation (pp. 71-90). Oxford: Elsevier Science.
  • Bongard, J., Zykov, V., & Lipson, H. (2006). Resilient machines through continuous self-modeling. Science, 314, 1118-1121.
  • Calvo Garzon, P. (2008). Towards a general theory of antirepresentationalism. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 59, 259-292.[WoS]
  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 181-204.[WoS]
  • Clark, A., & Grush, R. (1999). Towards a cognitive robotics. Adaptive Behavior, 7, 5-16.[Crossref]
  • Craver, C. F. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68, 31-55.
  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 741-765.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Fodor, J. (1994). The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, 342-353.[Crossref]
  • Gładziejewski, P. (2015). Action guidance is not enough; representations need correspondence too: A plea for a two-factor theory of representation. New Ideas in Psychology. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2015.01.005.[Crossref]
  • Grush, R. (1997). The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology, 10, 5-23.[Crossref]
  • Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 377-442.
  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Representational genera. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind (pp. 171-206). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Haselager, P., de Groot, A., & van Rappard, H. (2003). Representationalism vs. anti-representationalism: A debate for the sake of appearance. Philosophical Psychology, 16, 5-23.[Crossref]
  • Huang, Y., & Rao, R. (2011) Predictive coding. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2, 580-593.[Crossref]
  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Jones, M., & Love, B. C. (2011). Bayesian fundamentalism or enlightenment? On the explanatory status and theoretical contribution of Bayesian models of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 188-231.[WoS]
  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2001). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1-25.[WoS]
  • McDowell, J. (1994). The content of perceptual experience. Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 190-205.[WoS][Crossref]
  • Millikan, R.G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Miłkowski, M. (2013). Explaining the computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation (pp. 1-20). Oxford: Elsevier Science.
  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. F. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283-311.[WoS]
  • Ramsey,W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ramsey, W. (2015). Untangling two questions about representation. New Ideas in Psychology. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2015.01.004.[Crossref]
  • Shea, N. (2007). Consumers need information: Supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 404-435.[WoS]
  • Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449-508.[Crossref]
  • Tonneau, F. (2012). Metaphor and truth: A review of Representation reconsidered by W. M. Ramsey. Behavior and Philosophy, 39/40, 331-343.
  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.doi-10_1515_slgr-2015-0004
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.