Full-text resources of CEJSH and other databases are now available in the new Library of Science.
Visit https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


2020 | 23 | 4 | 7-33

Article title

Value-free paradise is lost. Economists could learn from artists

Content

Title variants

PL
Wolny od wartości raj został utracony. Ekonomiści mogli uczyć się od artystów

Languages of publication

Abstracts

EN
Despite the conclusions from the contemporary philosophy of science, many economists cherish the ideal of positive science. Therefore, value-free economics is still the central paradigm in economics. The first aim of the paper is to investigate economics’ axiomatic assumptions from an epistemological perspective. The critical analysis of the literature shows that the positive-normative dichotomy is exaggerated. Moreover, value-free economics is based on normative foundations that have a negative impact on individuals and society. The paper’s second aim is to show that economics’ normativity is not a problem because the discussion concerning values is possible and unavoidable. In this context, Weber and other methodologists are investigated. The conclusion of the paper is that science can thrive without strict methodological rules thanks to institutional mechanisms. Therefore, economists could learn from artists who accept the world without absolute rules. This perspective opens the possibility for methodological pluralism and normative approaches.

Year

Volume

23

Issue

4

Pages

7-33

Physical description

Dates

published
2020

Contributors

  • Wroclaw University of Economics and Business, Faculty of Economic Sciences, Department of Ecological Economics

References

  • Ainslie, G. (1975). Specious reward: A behavioral theory of impulsiveness and impulse control. Psychological Bulletin, 82(4), 463–496. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/h0076860
  • Akerlof, G. (2020). Sins of Omission and the Practice of Economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 58(2), 405–418.
  • Angner, E. (2019). We’re all behavioral economists now. Journal of Economic Methodology, 26(3), 195–207.
  • Backhouse, R. E. & Cherrier, B. (2017). The age of the applied economist: the transformation of economics since the 1970s. History of Political Economy, 49, 1–33.
  • Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1984). The complete works of Aristotle Vol. 2. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Becker, G. S. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Berg, N., & Gigerenzer, G. (2010). As-if behavioral economics: Neoclassical economics in disguise? History of Economic Ideas, 18(1), 133–165.
  • Blaug, M. (1992). The Methodology of Economics: Or How Economists Explain (2nd ed). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Blaug, M. (1997). Ugly Currents in Modern Economics. Options Politiques, 18(17), 3–8.
  • Boland, L. A. (1979). A critique of Friedman’s critics. Journal of Economic Literature, 17(2), 503–522.
  • Boldyrev, I. & Svetlova, E. (Eds.) (2016). Enacting Dismal Science: New Perspectives on the Performativity of Economics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Brickman, P., Coates, D. & Janoff-Bulman, R. (1978). Lottery winner and accident victims: is happiness relative? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36(8), 917–927. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.36.8.917
  • Brzeziński, M., Gorynia, M. & Hockuba, Z. (2008). Ekonomia a inne nauki społeczne na początku XXI w. Między imperializmem a kooperacją. Ekonomista, 2, 201–232.
  • Caldwell, B. J. (1992). A Critique of Friedman’s Methodological Instrumentalism: A Modification. Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology, 10, 119–128.
  • Callon, M. (2006). What does it mean to say that economics is performative? CSI Working Papers Series, no. 005, Centre de Sociologie de l’Innovation (CSI), Mines ParisTech.
  • Cedrini, M. & Fontana, M. (2018). Just another niche in the wall? How specialization is changing the face of mainstream economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 42(2), 427–451. https://doi.org/10.1093/cje/bex003
  • Colander, D. (2000). The death of neoclassical economics. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 22(2), 127–143. https://doi.org/10.1080/104277100 50025330
  • Colander, D., Holt, R. & Rosser, J. (2004). The Changing Face of Mainstream Economics. Review of Political Economy, 16(4), 485–499. https://doi.org/10.1080/0953825042000256702
  • Davis, J. B. (2006). The Turn in Economics: Neoclassical Dominance to Mainstream Pluralism. Journal of Institutional Economics, 2(1), 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744137405000263
  • Dow, S. C. (2012). Foundations for new economic thinking: A collection of essays. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Dun, F. Van (1986). Economics and the Limits of Value-Free Science. Reason Papers, 11, 17–32.
  • Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against method (3rd ed). New York–London: Verso.
  • Fiedor, B. & Ostapiuk, A. (2017). Utylitaryzm versus aksjologiczne i społeczne uwarunkowania wyborów ekonomicznych. In: E. Mączyńska, & J. Sójka (Eds.), Etyka i ekonomia. W stronę nowego paradygmatu (pp. 19–44). Warszawa: Polskie Towarzystwo Ekonomiczne.
  • Fourcade, M., Ollion, E. & Algan, Y. (2015). The superiority of economists. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 29(1), 89–114.
  • Friedman, M. (1953). Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Graupe, S. (2019). “Waging the war of ideas”: Economics as a textbook science and its possible influence on human minds. In: S. Decker, W. Elsner & S. Flechtner (Eds.), Advancing pluralism in teaching economics (pp. 173–191). London: Routledge.
  • Hands, D. W. (2001). Reflection Without Rules: Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hands, D. W. (2007). Effective tension in Robbins’s economic methodology. In: F. Cowell and A. Witztum (Eds.), Lionel Robbins’ essay on the nature and significance of economic science. 75th anniversary conference proceedings (pp. 152–168). London: London School of Economics and Political Science.
  • Hands, D. W. (2012). The positive-normative dichotomy and economics. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), Philosophy of economics (pp. 219–239). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • Hardt, Ł. (2020). Utylitaryzm, deontologia i etyka cnót: zbieżne czy przeciwstawne fundamenty etyczne ekonomii? Ekonomista, 2, 249–265.
  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hausman, D. M. (1998). Problems with realism in economics. Economics & Philosophy, 14(2), 185–213. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267100003837
  • Hausman, D. M. & McPherson, M. S. (2006). Economic Analysis, Moral Philosophy and Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hempel, C. G. (1945). Studies in the Logic of Confirmation (I.). Mind, 54(213), 1–26.
  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2017). Revisiting Friedman’s F53. Popper, Knight, and Weber. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12910/1/Friedmans%20F53.pdf
  • Hutchison, T. W. (1981). The Politics and Philosophy of Economics. New York: New York University Press.
  • Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292. https://doi.org/10.2307/1914185
  • Keynes, J. N. (1999). The scope and method of political economy. Kitchener, Ontario: Batoche Books.
  • Klamer, A., McCloskey, D. N. & Solow, R. M. (Eds.). (1988). The consequences of economic rhetoric. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Klappholz, K. (1964). Value Judgments and Economics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15(58), 97–114.
  • Klimczak, B. (2014). Aksjologiczne uwikłanie ekonomii. Annales. Etyka w Życiu Gospodarczym, 17(1), 9–21.
  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. In: T. S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. (1996). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (3rd ed). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Lakatos, I. (1980). The methodology of scientific research programmes. Philosophical Papers, Volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lawson, T. (2015). Essays on: The Nature and State of Modern Economics. Abingdon: Routledge.
  • Lazear, E. P. (2000). Economic imperialism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(1), 99–146. https://doi.org/10.1162/003355300554683
  • Madra, Y. M. (2016). Late Neoclassical Economics: The restoration of theoretical humanism in contemporary economic theory. New York: Routledge.
  • Mäki, U. (1995). Diagnosing McCloskey. Journal of Economic Literature, 33(3), 1300–1318.
  • Mäki, U. (2009). Unrealistic assumptions and unnecessary confusions: Rereading and rewriting F53 as a realist statement. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), The methodology of positive economics. Reflections on the Milton Friedman legacy (pp. 90–116). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mäki, U. (2012). Realism and antirealism about economics. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), Philosophy of economics (pp. 3–24). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • McCloskey, D. N. (1983). The rhetoric of economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 21(2), 481–517.
  • McCloskey, D. N. (1994). Knowledge and Persuasion in Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Megill, A. (1985). Prophets of Extremity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Derrida. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Merton, R. K. (1942). A note on science and democracy. Journal of Legal and Political Sociology, 1, 115–126.
  • Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s Qualitative Theory of Verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 166–177.
  • Mirowski, P. (2002). Machine dreams: Economics becomes a cyborg science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mongin, P. (2001). Value Judgments and Value Neutrality in Economics: A Perspective from Today. https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.200.2887&rep=rep1&type=pdf
  • Morgan, M. (2012). The world in the model: How economists work and think. Cambridge–New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Myrdal, G. (1970). Objectivity in Social Research. London: Gerald Duckworth.
  • Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science. Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Nietzsche, F. (1954). On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense. In: W. Kaufmann (Ed. & Transl.), The Portable Nietzsche. New York: Penguin Books.
  • Ostapiuk, A. (2017). Matematyzacja ekonomii – grzech pierworodny? Wieloaspektowa analiza wpływu i przyczyn. Ekonomia XXI wieku, 13(1), 91–104.
  • Ostapiuk, A. (2019a). Droga ekonomii wolnej od wartościowania do epistemologicznej pychy. Użycie i nadużycie matematyki przez ekonomistów. Zagadnienia Filozoficzne w Nauce, 67, 153–202.
  • Ostapiuk, A. (2019b). Human Now versus Human over Time. When Instrumental Rationality and Utility Are Not Enough. Panoeconomicus, 66(5), 633–657.
  • Ostapiuk, A. (2020). The Eclipse of Value-Free Economics. The concept of multiple self versus homo economicus. Wrocław: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Ekonomicznego we Wrocławiu.
  • Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: The decline of violence in history and its causes. New York: Penguin Group.
  • Poincaré, H. (2010). Science and method (F. Maitland, transl.). New York: Cosimo Classics.
  • Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.
  • Putnam, H. (2002). The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Quine, W. V. (1951). Main trends in recent philosophy: Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43.
  • Ratajczak, M. (2014). Ekonomia i edukacja ekonomiczna w dobie finansyzacji gospodarki. Ekonomista, 2, 207–219.
  • Reiss, J. (2013). Philosophy of economics: A contemporary introduction. Abingdon: Routledge.
  • Reiss, J. (2017). Fact-value entanglement in positive economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 24(2), 134–149. https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2017.1309749
  • Robbins, L. (1932). An essay on the nature & significance of economic science. London: Macmillan.
  • Rodrik, D. (2015). Economics rules: The rights and wrongs of the dismal science. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
  • Samuelson, P. (1952). Economic Theory and Mathematics – an Appraisal. American Economic Review, 42(2), 56–66.
  • Schweitzer, A. (1970). Typological Method in Economics: Max Weber’s Contribution. History of Political Economy, 2(1), 66–96.
  • Sen, A. K. (1970). Collective Choices and Social Welfare. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd.
  • Sen, A. K. (1987). On Ethics & Economics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • Sen, A. K. (1993). Internal Consistency of Choice. Econometrica, 61(3), 495–521.
  • Thaler, R. H. (1980). Toward a Positive Theory of Consumer Choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1(1), 39–60. https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-2681(80)90051-7
  • Thaler, R. H. (2015). Misbehaving: The Making of Behavioral Economics. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
  • Thaler, R. H. (2016). Behavioral economics: Past, present, and future. American Economic Review, 106(7), 1577–1600.
  • Weber, M. (1949). The methodology of the social sciences (E. Shils & H. Finch, transl.). Glencoe: The Free Press.
  • Weintraub, E. R. (2002). How economics became a mathematical science. Durham–London: Duke University Press.
  • Witztum, A. (2007). Ethics and the science of economics: Robbins’s enduring fallacy. In: F. Cowell and A. Witztum (Eds.), Lionel Robbins’ essay on the nature and significance of economic science. 75th anniversary conference proceedings (pp. 57–85). London: School of Economics and Political Science.
  • Wolin, S. S. (1981). Max Weber: Legitimation, Method, and the Politics of Theory. Political Theory, 9(3), 401–424.

Document Type

Publication order reference

Identifiers

Biblioteka Nauki
2028231

YADDA identifier

bwmeta1.element.ojs-doi-10_18778_1899-2226_23_4_01
JavaScript is turned off in your web browser. Turn it on to take full advantage of this site, then refresh the page.